9 - Evaluating Theories

All theories are false (Popper, 1959). So in one sense evaluating theories is a straightforward matter. However, some theories are more false than others. Furthermore, some theories have characteristics that tend to promote the advance of scientific knowledge. In this chapter, we examine what some of those characteristics are and how one goes about the process of identifying and building useful theories.

A theory is a concise statement about how we believe the world to be. Theories organize observations of the world and allow researchers to make predictions about what will happen in the future under certain conditions. Science is about the testing of theories, and the data that we collect as scientists should either implicitly or explicitly bear on theory.

There is, however, a great difference between theories in the hard sciences and theories in the soft sciences in their formal rigor. Formal theories are well established and incredibly successful in physics, but they play a lesser role in biology, and even less in psychology, where theories are often stated in verbal form. This has certainly been true historically, but some scientists, especially physicists, as well as laypeople, construe this fact to mean that formal theories are restricted to the hard sciences, particularly physics, while formalization is unattainable in the soft sciences. There is absolutely no reason to think so. Indeed, this is a pernicious idea that would permanently relegate psychology to second-class status.

Type Chapter Information Critical Thinking in Psychology , pp. 143 - 159 Publisher: Cambridge University Press Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akaike, H. ( 1973 ). Information theory and an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In Petrox , B. N. & Caski , F. (Eds.), Second international symposium on information theory (pp. 267–281). Budapest, Hungary : Akadémiai Kiadṍ.Google Scholar

Anderson , J. R. ( 1990 ). The adaptive character of thought . Hillsdale, NJ : Erlbaum.Google Scholar

Anderson , J. R., & Lebiere , C. ( 1998 ). The atomic components of thought . Mahwah, NJ : Erlbaum.Google Scholar

Anderson , J. R., & Schooler , L. J. ( 1991 ). Reflections of the environment in memory . Psychological Science , 2 , 396–408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Bozdogan , H. ( 1990 ). On the information-based measure of covariance complexity and its application to the evaluation of multivariate linear models . Communications in Statistics: Theory and Methods , 19 , 221–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Broadbent, D. ( 1987 ). Simple models for experimental situations. In Morris , P. (Ed.), Modeling cognition (pp. 169–185). London : Wiley.Google Scholar

Brown, S. C., & Craik, F. I. M. ( 2000 ). Encoding and retrieval of information. In Tulving , E. and Craik , F. I. M. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of memory (pp. 93–108). New York : Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Bush , V. ( 1945 ). Science – The endless frontier, appendix 3 . (Report of the Committee on Science and the Public Welfare). Washington, DC : U.S. Government Printing Office.Google Scholar

Cary , M., & Reder , L. M. ( 2003 ). A dual-process account of the list-length and strength-based mirror effects in recognition . Journal of Memory and Language , 49 , 231–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Cohen , J. ( 1994 ). The earth is round (p <.05) . American Psychologist , 49 , 997–1003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar